What It Means to Be a Marxist
What It
Means to Be a Marxist
By: Ramsin
Canon
Taken from:
Jacobin Magazine
It’s
unfortunate that there isn’t a better word for “Marxism.” Marx himself famously
once said that he himself was “not a Marxist” if certain askew interpretations
of his theories of historical materialism and capitalism were “Marxist.” Part
of the problem is that the theories and processes that Marx helped create are
too big to fall under a single -ism; Marx was a philosopher (and sort of
historian) of political economy, that is, the study of production and trade in
relationship to laws, customs, and human systems, whose theories helped inform
numerous other disciplines and practices: economics, sociology, history,
literature, and practical politics, among others.
The closest
analogy that I can think of is to what we would today call “Darwinism,” the
theories of nineteenth-century biologist Charles Darwin. Darwin didn’t invent
biology, paleontology, genetics, or any of the numerous disciplines and
practices that are informed by “Darwinism.” And in fact, there are many aspects
of classical “Darwinism” — the theories and conclusions arrived at by Darwin
and his immediate disciples — that have been outright revised or rejected by
people who today would still consider themselves “Darwinists.” Since Darwin
published On the Origin of Species and The Descent of Man, hundreds if not
thousands of scientists and philosophers have expanded on and improved Darwin’s
theories (the so-called “modern synthesis”) — obviously a necessity since
during Darwin’s lifetime there was no deep concept of molecular genetics.
It’s useful
to think of Marxism the same way. Marxism is not a detailed plan for how to
create socialism. Marxism isn’t a moral philosophy, in the way that the
Enlightenment philosophers and their progeny — like John Rawls — tried to build
up moral systems from first principles to determine what is the most “fair.” It
does not instruct us to engage in violent insurrection.
Marx,
through his analysis of human society, gave us an understanding of the laws
governing how society develops and how we can understand the process of
history. His theories of alienation and class struggle inform us as to the
causes of human misery and the obstacles to human flourishing. This is the
“historical materialism” that is the strongest single thread of his work.
Historical materialism is, simply stated, the theory that human societies develop
according to how the “forces of production” are ordered, and that the features
of a society will, ultimately, relate back to the ordering of the forces of
production. People will “relate” to the system of production as a class.
Therefore, the core conflict in society has been between classes on opposing
sides of the systems of production — this is the dialectical part of his
theory.
Just as
Darwin was not the first “evolutionist,” Marx was not by any means the first
socialist. And as with Darwin and the word “evolution,” “socialism” meant
something fairly different before Marx came along. Socialism was basically a
moral system, sometimes rooted in Christian values, utopian in character and
justified based on what was “fair” or “just.” Marx and Engels spent much of
their active years differentiating their theories from prior theories of
“utopian” socialism built on moral persuasion — Engels going as far as to
publish a book-length pamphlet on it.
Darwin
revolutionized existing theories of “evolution” by introducing the concept of
natural selection over geologic time — he should better be remembered for the
theory of natural selection than evolution; the early title of his book Origin
of Species was Natural Selection. In the same way, Karl Marx took existing
historical and philosophical analysis of human society and political economy
and applied an objective approach, from which he developed the theory of
historical materialism/dialectical materialism.
What
Marxism teaches us is simply to approach questions of society from a material
basis: how does human life persist? Through production of the goods and
services needed to live. How are these things produced under capitalist
society? Through exploitation of the labor of the working class, that is, by
requiring one class of people to sell their labor as a commodity to another
class to produce values. What is the result of this system? That workers are
“alienated” from their labor, meaning from much of their waking life,
constantly required to produce more and more with an ever-precarious access to
the means of subsistence.
If we want
to engage in political competition and analysis of what Marx would have called
“political economy,” there isn’t an alternative to Marxism that has anything
near its explanatory power or guidance. That said, I understand the caution
many socialists or social democrats may have to subscribing to “Marxism”:
Marx’s focus on class “struggle,” the “overthrow” of the capitalist class, and
the “dictatorship of the proletariat,” all of which may strike modern American
ears as prescriptions for violence and authoritarianism.
It’s
important to understand what Marx meant by these things.
The class
struggle doesn’t necessarily mean barricades in the streets and summary
execution of plutocrats. That these things can result from struggle is a
historical fact; but the “struggle” Marx is talking about is the social and
political competition between classes, which is always present: whether in the
form of wage demands, petitions, law changes, strikes, noncompliance, all the
way up to armed revolt. In the Manifesto, Marx describes how sometimes, the
capitalists will cave in to demands made via demonstrations and strikes; other
times, they will resist until concessions are forcibly extracted. Only the
relative strength of the sides determines the nature of the struggle. The whole
point of Marx’s method is to understand that the struggle is inherent to the
capitalist system; it is objective. How socialists choose strategically to win
the struggle depends on many factors, including the avenues available to them
to win changes to the system — this is subjective. Whether we like it or not,
the way commodities are produced under capitalism will always require struggle
between the classes; workers want more, capitalists want them to have less and
less.
As for
“overthrow,” Marx looks at how previous systems of production were ended and
changed into new forms: from hunter-gatherer to militarized, to slave chiefdoms
and kingdoms, to feudalism, and then to capitalism. It is true that these
transitions were generally marked by periods of violent competition; but (just
like with Darwinism) historical study has showed that the violent outbursts
were not the chief or only means of change. In fact, decades, sometimes
centuries, of smaller changes accumulated over time to put stress on existing
systems and bring about major changes. This is especially true of capitalism,
which arose in Europe not all at once after the French beheaded enough nobles,
but took place over an extended period beginning as far back as the fourteenth
century. The growth of state-like kingdoms, “free” trading cities, incremental
changes in technology, improvements in communications and logistics, and
changes in legal systems eroded the basis of feudalism; the French Revolution
was one part of a much longer and broader process of change.
Perhaps
most misunderstood is the idea of the “dictatorship of the proletariat,” which
comes from the Manifesto and a work called Critique of the Gotha Program, but
is often interpreted according to the later theories of Vladimir Lenin. The
dictatorship of the proletariat does not mean revolutionary terror against
class enemies and the death of freedom. It means something very simple: look
around you. Do you see how in “free market” democracies, political power is
monopolized (or nearly monopolized) by the ownership class? The “dictatorship”
of the proletariat just flips this. For Marxists, the dictatorship of the
proletariat simply means a period where political power is held in common for
the sole benefit of the working class. Getting to this point requires the
working class to realize it is in fact a single class, and acting in its own
interests. That this be accompanied by violent revolution isn’t necessary.
Dictatorship
is bad. We live under a form of dictatorship today: a dictatorship on behalf of
the capitalist class. This doesn’t mean working-class people have zero
freedoms; it means that the states we live in are specifically organized to
protect the capitalist system of social relations. Some people can own the
means of production and the rest of us have to sell our labor to survive. The
dictatorship of the proletariat just inverts this: it organizes the state to
preserve the common ownership of the means of production.
Marx and
Engels were critical of moral and “fairness” arguments for socialism because
they were ahistorical; they lacked a truly rational basis, and were therefore
just formed by ruling-class ideology. This isn’t unique to Marx, either: a
contemporary philosopher, Bernard Williams (no socialist himself) is among the
definitive moral philosophers who rejects the idea that we can reason our way
to morality. Historically, the forces of production — the thing that determines
human flourishing — had never been reordered through moral argument; it had
required engaging in struggle — in political competition. Marx was not trying
to provoke people into violence. He was merely exposing and acknowledging that
the forces of production create a class struggle, which will resolve in a change
to the forces of production.
As
socialists post-Marx, as with biologists post-Darwin, we merely accept the
material reality of the system in which we live. The forces of production rest
on exploitation to extract “surplus value” and requires commodifying labor,
which alienates workers. Struggle is inherent to the capitalist system. Only
when workers become conscious of themselves as a class and act on their own
behalf will they act to affirmatively end the system. There isn’t really a deep
question of morality here; this isn’t about fairness. It is about the struggle
between those who control their own destiny and are not alienated from their
means of subsistence (capitalists) and those who want this condition for
themselves, but are kept from it (the working class).
A word
about violence. Like most people, I abhor violence. Violence degrades its
perpetrators as it harms its victims. Marx does not prescribe violence,
although he does treat it as an obviously common outcome of periods of dramatic
change in the forces of production — that is, in periods of “overthrow.” We
need to ask ourselves whether major social change has ever avoided violence,
and where that violence came from. Consider the US Civil Rights Movement,
treated in historical memory as the best example of change from “nonviolence.”
But wasn’t there violence? The fact is that the state, and individuals, reacted
to the demands of black Americans with violence. There was violence during the
Civil Rights Movement; it just wasn’t meted out on a large scale by those
demanding their rights. And once those demands were won, there was “violence”
of another sort — when the state prosecuted and rounded up hate groups, like
the Klan for example, that was a sort of state “violence” we would consider appropriate.
Not to mention that attacks on freedom fighters, whether they were freedom
riders, civil rights lawyers, or a person protecting their home from a lynch
mob, always entailed violence.
And what
about the labor movement? From private guards to local police to the federal
army, violence was regularly called down on those engaging in struggle to win
rights in the workplace. The US labor movement, in fact, was particularly
marked by violence, even over its European counterparts, especially in the mountain
west where mining and energy concerns regularly called down armed forces to
break strikes. Struggle for the workers were strikes and noncompliance; the
reaction was violence.
In
historical struggle, those clinging to the system under attack are the first to
resort to violence. To be a Marxist doesn’t require belief in an armed uprising
to bring about a new world, in violent change or authoritarianism. It just
means acknowledging as a fact something that already exists: the class
struggle. The tactics and strategies workers employ to achieve class
consciousness and act to end the exploitative system are ours to determine.
Why
contemporary socialism is entwined with Marxism is this understanding of how
history moves and how it will move, based not on the moral arguments we make,
but on the objective conditions we live in. Workers will not struggle against
abstract principles but against living human beings with material interests. In
his Eighteenth Brumaire of Louis Napoleon, Marx wrote that “men make their own
history, but they do not make it as they please.” We can only change the world
if we truly understand the actual forces around us. If we want to change the
world, we need to be in it, to build from it; to truly be in it, we need to
understand it. That makes us Marxists.
Comments
Post a Comment